T h e o • p h i l o g u e

————–T h e o • p h i l o g u e————–


Three things you should know about the site:  (1)  T h e o • p h i l o g u e  is aimed at quality of critical research over quantity of rant posts, (2) it’s now postured by critical thinking and open-minded exploration of theology and philosophy and as such is not used to propagate or defend religious dogmas, and (3) the comment threads are where ideas are tested against contrary arguments or perspectives.  The dialogues are more important than the posts themselves, for in the exchange of arguments terms and logical connections are clarified and refined so that truths can be more clearly discerned.


Did Aquinas Hold a Forensic View of Justification?

In my latest post I argue that Aquinas did not hold a Protestant view of justification.  Protestant interpreters that see a forensic notion as central to Aquinas’ doctrine of justification based on his definition of justification as the remissio peccatorum [the forgiveness of sins] are deeply mistaken. But my article goes further than this, as I aim to establish that Aquinas’ use of forensic language that is often interpreted even by Catholic scholars of medieval theology to imply at least a purely forensic notion within Aquinas’ doctrine of justification are misleading.


 

Atheism According to Julian Baggini

Atheism__A Very Short Introduction by Julian Baggini__imageMy most recent post series was a summary and review of the chapters of a book written by Julian Baggini in defense of atheism but from a non-dogmatic author critical of the “new atheism.”

Baggini’s defense of atheism is important because it shows a kinder-gentler side of atheism that exemplifies true intellectual integrity over rhetoric and dogmatism.  Baggini grants as much to the theist as he possibly can and concludes that while there is evidence for theism, the evidence for atheism is much stronger.  While making his case chapter-by-chapter, he still holds out the possibility that he could be mistaken.  His book is a perfect introduction onto the subject matter of atheism, as it avoids extremes and aims to play fair.  I offer mostly praise but some criticism, concluding that how Baggini makes his case for atheism demonstrates a lack of familiarity with some of the strongest counter-arguments.  In spite of shortcomings (and who is above shortcomings?), however, if I were teaching a class on philosophy this book would without doubt be required reading for all my students.

I give Julian Baggini’s book * * f i v e   s t a r s* * * without any hesitation as the best introduction to the subject matter for those seeking to learn it for the first time.  It’s not too technical or erudite so as to burden the reader with thinking she must now read 100 other books to really “get it,” yet Baggini’s case for atheism is the case of an established philosopher not a polemic rhetorician.  He manages to neatly encapsulate a good mixture between classic critiques of theism and more up-to-date perspectives.

UPDATE (1): BAGGINI OFFERS RECOGNITION
Julian Baggini (the author) has tipped his hat of appreciation via twitter for my engagement with his book.  Given that I offered some substantial criticism in my last few posts about the book that I believe undermine his overall strategy for defending atheism, his kind gesture only further exemplifies my point about his good will.
UPDATE (2): BAGGINI RESPONDS TO CRITICISM
Julian Baggini (the author) indirectly responded to one of my criticisms via Twitter about how to understand the atheist position (can we understand atheism as a positive position as Baggini aims to do?).  I had argued that atheism by modern definition is negative because it is by definition a rejection of belief in the existence of God, and that Baggini’s supposed “positive” aspects of atheism are not inherent to atheism as part of its meaning or position, but happen rather to accompany or compliment atheism in his beliefs.  I argued further that he  misapplies and misunderstands the etymological fallacy in attempting to handle objections.  He tweeted a reply (but without tweeting it directly to me): “‘No’ is never wholly negative.  Every No is a Yes to the alternative.  To agree to 1 thing is to deny what acceptance excludes.  Say yes to no!”  But I would counter that saying “No” to a belief cannot inherently contain the meaning of “yes” to an alternative belief unless there is only one alternative.  But saying “No” to theism doesn’t necessarily or logically entail the acceptance of an alternative.  One might say “no” to belief in God and “yes” to any given number of philosophically sophisticated alternatives which could themselves be either negative or positive.  What unifies Atheists in their “No” is not a consensus or solidarity about the alternative to theism, since no singular alternative can be seen as the Atheist alternative.  For this reason, the “No” of Atheism per se, is simply a “No,” not a “Yes” to an alternative.  The act of rejecting a belief as false per se gives no necessary indication of what is true.
•••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••

What is Atheism? :: A Book Review of Julian Baggini’s “Atheism: A Very Short Introduction”

The Case for Atheism :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Atheist Ethics :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Atheist Purpose and Meaning :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Atheism in History :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Against Religion? :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Concluding Remarks :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Can A Theist Appreciate Baggini’s Atheism? :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Is Atheism Really a Positive Worldview? :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction

Does Atheist Julian Baggini Consider the Strongest Counter Evidence? :: Book Review of Julian Baggini’s book Atheism: A Very Short Introduction


Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica

Thomas Aquinas: Summa Theologica :: My most recent posts were (1) an examination of the use of language of forgiveness in Thomas Aquinas with respect to his doctrine of justification entitled Remissio Peccatorum in Thomas Aquinas’ Doctrine of Justification: Did Aquinas Hold a Forensic View of Justification? and (2)  a summary of Thomas Aquinas’s doctrine of justification as found in the ten questions of article 113 in the prima secunda of Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologica: “Of the Effects of Grace.”  This is the latest addition to my ever-increasing number of posts where I’ve summarized some article relating to grace in Thomas’ Summa.

•••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••

Thomas Aquinas on Theological Virtues: Summa Theologica

Thomas Aquinas on The Cause and Efficacy of Grace :: Summa TheologicaAIR_20140703_00000_1

Thomas Aquinas on Operating, Co-Operating, and Prevenient Grace :: Summa Theologica

Thomas Aquinas on the Essence of Grace :: Summa Theologica

Thomas Aquinas on the Doctrine of Justification :: Summa Theologica

• a u d i o p o s t • :: On the Necessity of Grace by Thomas Aquinas

Other posts on Aquinas in Summa include:

          Aquinas’s Posture of Humility to the Tradition

          Aquinas the Calvinist (via Eastern Orthodoxy?)


 The Demerits of Utilitarianism

UtilitarianismMore people are reading my post Utilitarianism: What is it? Why does it not work? than ever before because of the discussion in the comment thread where my arguments and perspective are challenged by a welcome visitor who argues that I haven’t proven Utilitarianism to be untrue.  In the end, I argue that this visitor is working with an understanding of utilitarianism that doesn’t ultimately base right or wrong on consequences, but bases the key criterion for right and wrong in the human intention—the intention to effect the best consequences.  This one thread may have captured  T h e o • p h i l o g u e ‘ s  most sustained debate over the merits of the utilitarian ethic.  Here is an excerpt from this discussion of one of my arguments I coined “The Omniscience Requirement” of Utilitarianism, which I argue makes Utilitarianism an impossible ethical guideline for action.


• The Utilitarian paradigm requires for us to do what will cause “greater pleasure (and less pain)”
• In order for us to do what will cause “greater pleasure” we must know what the consequences of our actions will be.
• In order to know what the consequences of our actions will be, we would need to know immediate and future consequences.
• But it is impossible to know the full range of all future consequences for any given action or set of actions by an individual or society.
• Therefore, we cannot know what the immediate and future consequences of our actions will actually be.
• Therefore, we cannot know what will cause the “greater pleasure.”
• Therefore, we cannot do what is required from us in the Utilitarian paradigm.
• Therefore, utilitarianism is impossible.


 An Eastern Theology of Justification

John Chrysostom 3I just added my article on the doctrine of justification in John Chrysostom:  The Superiority of Faith: John Chrysostom’s Eastern Theology of Justification.  Here I am concerned to show that although Chrysostom teaches a doctrine of justification by grace through faith (and even uses the language of “faith alone”), he has an Eastern theology of justification vastly different from the Reformation’s version of the doctrine, and uses the same language in a way that actually undermines the key concerns of Reformation doctrines of justification.

In the footnotes I criticize and correct various authors who have misinterpreted Chrysostom in various ways on this subject: and here I correct not just Protestants who proof text Chrysostom’s language and assume it has Protestant meaning, but also ecumenical uses of Chrysostom that somehow fail to illuminate the most important dynamics in his theology of justification.  In the end, Chrysostom’s theology of justification is neither Catholic nor Protestant, but Eastern.  To find out what this means, and why I come to this conclusion, you will have to read my article.

You can see other academic contributions on my PDF Catalog, where you can download the full articles.

%d bloggers like this: